4. The Rule of Law
Formulations
Broadest – people should be ruled by law; law should be capable of ruling people (guiding their behaviour by being clear & prospective)
Narrower – government should be subject to law (harder to achieve)
BUT if government is by definition government authorised by law – then this becomes tautology?
Thick v thin conceptions – formal requirements as to institutions (prospectivity, independence of judiciary, etc) v substantive requirements as to equality in substance of laws etc
‘thin’ conception (law governs all in a way that is predictable & allows citizens to conduct their affairs)
complemented by ‘thicker’ conception requiring certain procedural rights – no good having proper norms if not properly administered / adjudicated
Stems from features of legal order
Comprehensiveness; purported supremacy
Definition, specificity, clarity – and therefore predictability
Goldsworthy —Legal principle or political ideal?
Legal principle – judicially enforceable – invoked in Canada as basis for judicial review of legislation
Ironically, using rule of law as (bare) basis for invalidating legislation would breach requirement for certainty & predictability in rule of law
Political aspiration – constitutional insofar as conventions require compliance
Does not bind legislatures any more than other political principles (like equality or other conventions)
Distinct from question whether rule of law compatible with political sovereignty
And even if it is, whether democracy is more important than the rule of law
Rule of law can exist in systems without democracy – would the case for subjugation of legislative power to bills of rights be stronger?
Even if they are, does not follow that democracy ‘trumps’ – just that countervailing factor
History
Plato — philosopher king & benevolent monarchy, but still hoped that law would have authority in itself
“where the law is subject to some other authority and has none of its won, the collapse of the state is not far off” <> “if law is the master of the government and the government its slave, then the situation is full of promise”
Aristotle — first pure advocate of rule of law
Deuteronomy imposed some limits on Jewish kings — although never implemented or enforced
Raz — Thin conception
Raz — Fallacies re rule of law
It does not have overriding importance
For good legal system has to be complemented by democracy, justice, equality, human rights, etc
Rule of law does not equate to rule of good law — otherwise becomes a truism
System can comply with the rule of law and make many bad laws
Waldron —Rule-book conception — texts & precedents of law applied with certainty & without fear or favour
One of a cluster of ideals constituting political morality — together with human rights, democracy, and free markets
Rule of law is fundamental
Democracy cannot exist except with procedures of election secured by law
Markets require law governing property & contract
UDHR preamble states essential that must be protected by rule of law
Rule of law is older — since Aristotle, well before human rights & democracy fully developed
Rule of law required but not sufficient for good government
Cf Hayek – uses rule of law to call for good laws – in particular to prohibit government interference with economy – rule of law should not be mobilised to particular political agenda
Definition of ‘good’ necessarily differs from person to person
Pursuit of any particular social goal cannot be inconsistent with rule of law
FA Hayek’s definition – government bound by rules fixed & announced beforehand, which are sufficiently certain to allow individuals to plan their affairs
Says nothing about how law ought to be made – democratic structures, etc
Historical origins – rule of law came about well before democracy
Brings in judicial review through ultra vires philosophy, requires independence of the courts
Really just an exercise in taxonomy – but gives the principle some meaning
Extremely unjust laws that are prospective, promulgated, clear and stable are not objectionable on rule of law grounds
Rule of law is necessary but not sufficient for justice
Thin justification does not require any particular substantive limitation on legislative power – justifies only very limited, procedural review of legislation
Impractical – requirements for publicity of laws, stability, clarity, cannot be absolute (but does this negate possibility of review?)
Eg Ashworth / France – defence of ignorance of law if reasonable
Prospectivity – justified in certain circs & should leave to parliament to decide
Obviously shouldn’t have judicial mandate to invalidate on that ground alone –
eg war crimes legislation is retrospective but justified
British Parliament 1965 reversing right to compensation retrospectively
Cf. Gaudron J in Tampa special leave application
Changing common law in criminal cases – has retrospective effect (eg Issa & Elias) – ‘fairy-tale’ of declaratory theory of common law
From political perspective – desirable in the pursuit of the aspiration that have constitutional requirement to put retrospective legislation to plebiscite (if parliament derives sovereignty from the people)
“Functional” conception — variant of thin view
Rule of law <> Rule of man
IE rule of law strongest when men have least discretion
Still says nothing about virtue of laws — just encourages certainty at expense of flexibility
As a negative value
Rule of law essentially a negative value – minimises dangers inherent in the existence of law
Conformity does not cause good but avoids evil
No necessary connection between law & morality
TRS Allan — Response to Raz’s ‘negative value’ conception
Reduces to requirement that society be governed by ‘law’ – bare conception that adds nothing to requirement for ‘law’ of a kind
BUT that is true, and it has follow-on consequences as described above; still has substance; says more than requirement for source of authorisation
Knife analogy –
sharp knife is a good knife, even if can be used for bad purposes – laws conforming with rule of law are good laws in a sense, even if bad in content
Guarantees law/knife’s ability to function – even if functions in a bad way – supports instrumental value, not moral value
Pre-requisite for law/knife’s ability to function in a morally good way is to function at all
Finnis — Criticism of knife analogy
Finnis rejects that rule of law simply enables efficiency – eg requirement for stability & subjection of government to rules decreases efficiency to guarantee good government
BUT knife analogy isn’t efficiency in the sense of executing the sovereign’s will – is efficiency in sense of enhancing rules’ ability to govern behaviour of individuals & government
Nor is it Barber’s efficiency in the sense of achieving virtuous outcomes
Criticisms of thin conception
would allow ‘chronic lawless violence’ inflicted on some citizens against others
= formal equality before the law
concerns extent of appropriate regulation of activity – also raises question about applicability of rule of law to private actors
Does rule of law require some minimum standard of regulation? Probably not – that is supplied by other ideals – eg equality, democracy (indirectly)
Thick conception
Finnis —Natural law conception – BUT seems to put the cart before the horse – law must be subject to certain (rule-of-law) restraints to be legitimate, that legitimacy has a biproduct of fairness // cf law must be fair to be legitimate, that fairness requires certain restraints
Authority of law depends on ability to secure justice – eg criminal law’s reliance on proportionality, procedural fairness, etc
TRS Allan —Rule of law = maintenance of conditions consistent with liberty of individual & equality of liberty for all
BUT this is charged with political ideals, extends beyond narrow rule of law conception
Is the kind of conception that is mobilised against the Regulatory & Welfare State
Dicey & later Hayek conceive rule of law as relationship between law & liberty
Waldron — rule of law requiring good procedures v good outcomes
Waldron — Proceduralist conception — procedures of law will be adhered to; certainty of outcome less important than certainty of procedure
Could be framed as “thin” conception — procedures are in the rule book as well
Alternatively, “thicker” rule of law conception as presumes good procedures, involving proper & considered deliberative procedures, and therefore considered & tempered outcomes
Purpose of constructing good procedures is to ensure good outcomes
<> even thin conception — must also have some core minimum of good procedural requirements unless consistent arbitrariness is to satisfy rule of law
Dworkin — the rights conception (outcomes) — moral & political rights of citizens, as against each other & the State, be recognised in positive law & enforceable through institutions
If only legal rights — would be thin “Rule-book” conception
Expressly thick — equates rule of law with rule of good law (ie law that accurately represents morality)
“requires, as part of the ideal of law, that the rules in the rule-book capture and enforce moral rights”
Encourages each individual to suppose that his relations with other citizens & government are matters of (moral) justice
Overtly focuses on legal outcomes rather than procedures
Although rights are procedural...