xs
This website uses cookies to ensure you get the best experience on our website. Learn more

#10529 - Foundations Of Judicial Review - Administrative Law

Notice: PDF Preview
The following is a more accessible plain text extract of the PDF sample above, taken from our Administrative Law Notes. Due to the challenges of extracting text from PDFs, it will have odd formatting.
See Original

There is a good deal of literature concerning the ‘constitutional foundations’ of judicial review. In these lectures, we will address three main sets of issues.

  • The nature of the question. When we inquire about the constitutional foundations of judicial review, what exactly are we asking about?

    • What gives the courts constitutional authority to strike down executive action?

    • What gives them the right to determine what action is unlawful?

    • How do courts work out what action is unlawful?

    • What, if anything, constrains the courts when they do this?

    • What is the legal nature and source of the limits upon executive power enforced upon the courts by judicial review?

    • How are these powers reconciled with statute and constitutional principles such as sovereignty?

  • The relevance of the question. Does is matter what the constitutional basis of judicial review is—and, if so, why?

    • Yes:

      • It relates to fundamental Qs such as parliamentary sovereignty.

      • Basis of JR might influence the content of the rules applied by courts.

      • Relationship between basis of JR and the effectiveness of ouster clauses?

      • Relationship between the basis of JR and availability of ‘collateral challeneg’?

    • NO:

      • Purely theoretical debate.

      • Basis of review doesn’t influence the content of rules applied by the courts.

      • Doesn’t really affect how courts decide cases.

  • The answers to the question. What, then, are the constitutional foundations of judicial review?

    • There are competing answers to the question.

      • UV model.

      • Modified UV model.

      • Common law model.

      • JR as a ‘constitutional fundamental’.

The principle is an attempt at justifying Judicial Review of executive acts and decisions.

‘Courts may intervene whenever a decision maker acts ultra vires – that is, ‘beyond the powers’ conferred by legislation – while intra vires acts are lawful and unimpeachable. Thus the principle provides a powerful justification for the exercise of supervisory jurisdiction, because it argues that courts are only carrying out parliament’s intentions when enforcing the limits that are found (expressly or impliedly) within statute.

Note the following points about the ultra vires model:

  • The ‘central principle of administrative law’: Wade and Forsyth

  • Key question for court: is decision within conferred authority?

The key question is whether the administrative act or decision under challenge within or outside the authority conferred upon the agency by parliament through the medium of the relevant statute.

  • But how is the court to answer this question?

Through the interpretation of statute – interpreting the legislation in order to determine the extent of the agency’s power.

W&F: Where the empowering act lays down limits expressly, this just involves construing statutory language and applying it to the facts.

  • e.g. ‘Land may be taken by compulsory purchase, provided it is not part of a park’. The court need only determine whether the land is part of a park and decide accordingly. This is uncontroversial - a decision maker’s decision to purchase land in Hyde Park could be struck down as ultra vires.

But where an act confers discretionary power on a decision maker, the question is not so simple.

  • e.g. ‘Land may be taken by compulsory purchase, providing the Minister doesn’t think it is part of a Park’. Taking the statutory language literally, if the Minister states he is of the opinion that Hyde Park isn’t a park, the court in applying the statute could not say that he is operating outside of the confines of his jurisdiction. However principles of good administration require that there can be no malpractice of this kind. The court will intervene and determine the decision to be ultra vires if it was taken unreasonably, in bad faith, or on no proper evidence – that is the developed grounds of judicial review. This can only be achieved through the art of statutory construction. It is presumed that parliament did not intend that such abuses could take place, so certain safeguards against abuse are implied within the act.

As with substance – whether discretion has been exercised UV – so with procedure, too.

  • e.g. It is assumed that parliament when conferring power intends that it be used fairly and in line with due consideration of the rights and interests of those that may be adversely affected. This means judges read all statutes as having implied terms relating to, for example, procedural fairness. Parliament effectively legislates against a background of pre-made judicial principles pertaining to fairness – and in creating these principles, judges take parliaments agreement for granted.

Although, as we will see, the ultra vires model has been heavily criticised—to such an extent that it does not, in its unreconstructed form, enjoy any serious support amongst commentators—it does have certain attractive features.

First, it enjoys a degree of judicial support—although it is certainly arguable that judicial reliance upon the rhetoric of ‘ultra vires’ does not necessarily imply thoroughly thought-through support for the ultra vires model. See, for example, myriad references to ‘ultra vires’ in the speeches in Boddington v British Transport Police [1999] 2 AC 143, and, in particular, Lord Steyn’s comments (at 171):

Leaving to one side the separate topic of judicial review of non-legal powers exercised by non statutory bodies, I see no reason to depart from the orthodox view that ultra vires is "the central principle of administrative law" as Wade and Forsyth … described it.

Note also Lord Browne-Wilkinson’s comments in R v Hull University Visitor, ex parte Page [1993] AC 682 at 701:

The fundamental principle [of judicial review] is that the courts will intervene to ensure that the powers of public decision-making bodies are exercised lawfully. In all cases . . . this intervention . . . is based on the proposition that such powers have been conferred on the decision maker on the underlying assumption that the powers are to be exercised only within the jurisdiction conferred, in accordance with fair procedures and, in a Wednesbury sense ... reasonably. If the decision maker exercises his powers outside the jurisdiction conferred, in a manner which is procedurally irregular or is Wednesbury unreasonable, he is acting ultra vires his powers and therefore unlawfully.

He anchors what courts do in underlying legislation: ‘powers conferred on underlying assumption. But there is ambiguity as to whether these judges are endorsing the specific doctrine – or just using ‘ultra vires’ as a synonym for ‘unlawful’ – without actually referring to the concept itself.

Secondly, in some (but, as we will see, not all) circumstances, the ultra vires doctrine seems accurately to capture what is going on, in terms of courts reviewing executive action for compliance with standards which are laid down, or otherwise apparent from, the legislation—and that seeking to explain what the courts are doing in any other way would be unconvincing. There are clearly many instances of the courts following the ultra vires doctrine – or at least doing what the doctrine would tell them to do, if they were following it. Consider, for instance, the following cases:

  • R (A) v Croydon London Borough Council [2009] UKSC 8, [2009] 1 WLR 2557

Every local authority shall provide accommodation for any child in need within their area who appears to them to require accommodation as a result of (…). The question was whether the claimant in the case was a child. The supreme court said that it was within their jurisdiction to decide on whether C was a child.

This is a clear example of a court deciding on the legality of administrative action with reference to a statute – they are following, therefore, the kind of process that the ultra vires principle says JR is all about.

  • Lloyd v McMahon [1987] AC 625

Lord Keith decided that oral hearings were not necessary before statutory auditors issued ceterficates of a penal nature to councillors by reference to the lack of an explicit provision for it within the statute – noting that explicit provisions had been found in other similar statutes. The case demonstrates a clear link between what the court decides and what the statute says – applying the thinking of the ultra vires principle.

  • R v Secretary of State for the Home Department, ex parte Venables

Home Secretary set the tariff period of child murderer Jon Venables, on a once and for all basis. It was held that in doing so, the minister was acting unlawfully – the statute imposed a duty to have regard to the welfare of the child or young person – requiring ongoing review of the tariff period – not setting once and for all. He was acting ultra vires.

This is not, however, to suggest that all instances of judicial review can readily be related to the terms of the relevant legislation. This point is developed below.

Thirdly, viewed from the perspective of judicial politics, the ultra vires model is highly convenient:

  • Judges as ‘modest underworkers’: Cotterell, ‘Judicial Review and Legal Theory’ in Richardson and Genn (eds), Administrative Law and Government Action (Oxford 1994) at 16

Cottrell suggests that the judges play a role as ‘modest underworkers’. The implementation of parliamentary intention simply protects judges against charges of activism or judicial supremacism.

  • ‘...[T]he logic behind the doctrine provides an inherent rationale for...

Unlock the full document,
purchase it now!
Administrative Law

More Administrative Law Samples

Administrative Law Theory Notes Availability Of Claims For Judic... Bias Impartiality And Independen... Constitutional Foundations Notes Control Of Discretion Notes Deference Quick Notes Discretionary Powers Notes Discretion Fettering Notes Discretion Wednesbury Proporti... Errors Of Fact Notes Fair Procedures Notes Foundations Of Judicial Review ... Hra1998 How It Works And Its I... Institutions And Accountability ... Introduction To Admin Notes Jr Procedure Notes Jr Theory Notes Jurisdiction Cases Jurisdiction Notes Jurisdiction Notes Jurisdiction Of Judicial Review ... Jurisdiction Notes Jurisdiction Problem Question N... Jurisdiction Review For Error ... Jurisdiction Revision Notes Legitimate Expectation Notes Legitimate Expectations And Esto... Legitimate Expectations Cases Legitimate Expectations Notes Legitimate Expectations Notes Legitimate Expectations Notes Legitimate Expectations Problem... Legitimate Expectations Revision... Natural Justice Notes Natural Justice Essay Natural Justice Notes Private And Public Divide Notes Procedural Exclusivity Notes Procedural Fairness Notes Procedural Fairness Notes Procedural Fairness Reasons And ... Procedural Fairness Rule Agains... Procedure Cases Procedure Reading Notes Proceedural Fairness Notes Reasons Problem Question Notes ... Relevancy & Proprietary Problem... Restriction On Remedies Problem... Retention Of Discretion And Abus... Retention Of Discretion Problem... Review Of Discretion Notes Review Of Discretion Quick Notes Scope Of Judicial Review Proble... Standing And Sufficient Interest... Standing Notes Standing Notes Standing Notes Standing Quick Notes Substantive Review Cases Substantive Review Notes Substantive Review Notes Substantive Review Notes Substantive Review Problem Ques... Substantive Review Revision Notes The Giving Of Reasons Reading Notes Theory Notes Theory Of Administrative Law Notes Validity And Collateral Challeng...