xs
This website uses cookies to ensure you get the best experience on our website. Learn more

#10526 - Retention Of Discretion And Abuse I - Administrative Law

Notice: PDF Preview
The following is a more accessible plain text extract of the PDF sample above, taken from our Administrative Law Notes. Due to the challenges of extracting text from PDFs, it will have odd formatting.
See Original

Once it is established that the decision-maker has legal power (jurisdiction) and he or she exercises that power fairly, the question arises whether the decision-maker exercised their power reasonably (in the broad sense). And that is what we will be concerned with in these lectures on the control of discretionary power.

All power has legal limits. This is a requirement of the rule of law; and it is the task of the courts to police those limits. But Parliament constantly confers upon public authorities powers which on their face might seem absolute and arbitrary. The courts have refused to countenance arbitrary power unfettered discretion.

The courts have woven a network of restrictive principles that require statutory powers to:

  1. be exercised reasonably and in good faith;

  2. for proper purposes only; and

  3. in accordance with the spirit as well as the letter of the empowering Act.

Most of the principles deployed by the courts to control the exercise of discretion are ancient. They can be traced at least to Rooke’s Case in the 16th century. The Commissioners of Sewers had levied charges for repairing a riverbank, but they had thrown the whole charge on one adjacent owner instead of apportioning it among all the owners benefited. In law they had power to levy charges in their discretion.

But this charge was disallowed. Coke CJ said:

“. . and notwithstanding the words of the commission give authority to the commissioners to do according to their discretions, yet their proceedings ought to be limited and bound with the rule of reason and law. For discretion is a science or understanding to discern between falsity and truth, between wrong and right, between shadows and substance, between equity and colourable glosses and pretences, and not to do according to their wills and private affections….”

Coke LJ: discretion has legal limits. All power is circumscribed by the rule of law. One of the ways in which that idea exemplifies itself is in the idea of the retention of discretion.

Elsewhere he distinguishes between “the golden and straight metwand of the law” and the “crooked cord of private opinion that the vulgar call discretion” (4 Inst 41; Co. Litt 227b).

Pursuant to this rule of reason discretionary power must be retained in the hands of those to which it was entrusted by Parliament. Thus the decision-maker must not unlawfully delegate the power; or surrender or abdicate the power to another; or act under another’s dictation; or adopt an over rigid policy; or restrict the discretion by contract (or by estoppel). A key principle in Administrative Law is that of retention of discretion – Parliament chooses who should exercise a power and make decisions, and only this person should have that discretion. Areas where this principle of retention may come into play include prohibition, delegation, fettering, over-rigid policy etc. The principle does not deal with the substance of the decision, but with ensuring that the correct person is making it.

Elliott perceives that the rules of administrative law that have developed in this context serve two distinct but related objectives.

  1. They require that decision-making is carried out by the specific agency tow which that discretion was, confided (so the transfer or delegation of discretion is prohibited); and

  2. ensure that the agency has at its disposal the full discretion which was granted to it (thereby precluding behaviour, such as the adoption of rigid policies or the entry into contracts, which limits that discretion).

An authority can fail to give its mind to a case, and thus fail to exercise its discretion lawfully, by blindly following a policy laid down in advance. The raison d’être of discretionary power is that it permits decision makers to respond appropriately to the demands of particular situations. It is a fundamental rule that discretion must be brought to bear on every case: each one must be considered on its own merits and decided as the public interest requires at the time.

At the same time like cases should be treated alike; and it is right for administrative decision-makers should develop policies in order that their powers be exercised consistently. A tension therefore arises: to what extent may administrators legitimately structure their decision-making in this way, given that the very essence of discretionary power is the individualisation of decision making to circumstances?

Here are some contrasting views: R v Port of London Authority ex parte Kynoch [1919] KB 176 at 184:

“There are on the one hand cases where a tribunal in the honest exercise of its discretion has adopted a policy, and, without refusing to hear an applicant, intimates to him what its policy is, and that after hearing him it will in accordance with its policy decide against him, unless there is something exceptional in his case. I think counsel for the applicants would admit that, if the policy has been adopted for reasons which the tribunal may legitimately entertain, no objection could be taken to such a course. On the other hand there are cases where a tribunal has passed a rule, or come to a determination, not to hear any application of a particular character by whomsoever made. There is a wide distinction to be drawn between these two classes.” Bankes LJ

This analysis is useful to the extent that it draws a distinction between a policy which is flexible, and a rule which is applied so rigidly as to remove any genuine discretion. However, to the extent that it implies two wholly distinct categories of case, Bankes LJ’s analysis is too simplistic. Between the two extremes, it is self evident that a there will exist a spectrum of policies of differing degrees of rigidity. It is the court’s function to determine – taking account of contextual factors such as the nature of the decision making function in question – whether a given policy is sufficiently flexible to be legitimate.

British Oxygen Co Ltd v. Minister of Technology [1971] AC 610 The minister, having been given a discretionary power to provide business with grants to assist the purchase of industrial machinery and having resolved to adopt a policy to make no grants in respect of machinery costing less than 25, refused assistance to the claimant company, who had spent some 4 million on numerous items of equipment costing 20 each. Held, the minister had acted lawfully – it was inevitable that large departments called upon to decide cases would ‘evolve a policy so precise that it could well be called a rule’.

“But the circumstances in which discretions are exercised vary enormously and that passage cannot be applied literally in every case. The general rule is that anyone who has to exercise a statutory discretion must not “shut his ears to an application” (Bankes LJ [see [1919] 1 KB 176 at 183]). I do not think there is any great difference between a policy and a rule. There may be cases where an officer or authority ought to listen to a substantial argument reasonably presented urging a change of policy. What the authority must not do is to refuse to listen at all. But a Ministry or large authority may have had to deal already with a multitude of similar applications and then they will almost certainly have evolved a policy so precise that it could well be called a rule. There can be no objection to that, provided the authority is always willing to listen to anyone with something new to say – of course I do not mean to say that there need be an oral hearing. In the present case the respondent’s officers have carefully considered all that the appellants have had to say and I have no doubt that they will continue to do so.” Lord Reid

Bankes LJ suggests that a policy admits of an exception, but a rule does not. Nevertheless Lord Reid in British Oxygen says that ‘I do not think there is any great difference between a policy and a rule. (p3) One can see how a decision making process wanting to decide fairly would have a measure of consistency/precedent, so that like cases are decided alike. But it does mean that the rule begins to be applied with more rigidity. The British Oxygen approach demonstrates a rather more indulgent, less restrictive attitude towards policy-oriented decision-making. It ascribes a generous role to policy, allowing it to become the norm on which decision-making is founded, provided of course that the decision maker is willing to make exceptions in appropriately unusual cases.

In seeking to determine whether this residual flexibility is present, and thus capable of legitimising the decision maker’s policy-based approach, the courts are unsurprisingly more interested in substance rather than form. Consequently, even where the decision maker claims to depart from policy in particular circumstances, the court may require evidence that this is actually happening (and in the absence of such evidence may conclude that the policy is being applied over-rigidly).

Can these dicta be reconciled? Context is, as so often, important. More rigid policies will be justified were the decision-making process requires consistency. Where there are many essentially similar cases to be decided…like cases must be treated alike. Ultimately it is a question of the close construction of the relevant statutes. Elliott suggests that there may be situations in which it is lawful to operate a policy which does not yield even in the face...

Unlock the full document,
purchase it now!
Administrative Law

More Administrative Law Samples

Administrative Law Theory Notes Availability Of Claims For Judic... Bias Impartiality And Independen... Constitutional Foundations Notes Control Of Discretion Notes Deference Quick Notes Discretionary Powers Notes Discretion Fettering Notes Discretion Wednesbury Proporti... Errors Of Fact Notes Fair Procedures Notes Foundations Of Judicial Review N... Foundations Of Judicial Review ... Hra1998 How It Works And Its I... Institutions And Accountability ... Introduction To Admin Notes Jr Procedure Notes Jr Theory Notes Jurisdiction Cases Jurisdiction Notes Jurisdiction Notes Jurisdiction Of Judicial Review ... Jurisdiction Notes Jurisdiction Problem Question N... Jurisdiction Review For Error ... Jurisdiction Revision Notes Legitimate Expectation Notes Legitimate Expectations And Esto... Legitimate Expectations Cases Legitimate Expectations Notes Legitimate Expectations Notes Legitimate Expectations Notes Legitimate Expectations Problem... Legitimate Expectations Revision... Natural Justice Notes Natural Justice Essay Natural Justice Notes Private And Public Divide Notes Procedural Exclusivity Notes Procedural Fairness Notes Procedural Fairness Notes Procedural Fairness Reasons And ... Procedural Fairness Rule Agains... Procedure Cases Procedure Reading Notes Proceedural Fairness Notes Reasons Problem Question Notes ... Relevancy & Proprietary Problem... Restriction On Remedies Problem... Retention Of Discretion Problem... Review Of Discretion Notes Review Of Discretion Quick Notes Scope Of Judicial Review Proble... Standing And Sufficient Interest... Standing Notes Standing Notes Standing Notes Standing Quick Notes Substantive Review Cases Substantive Review Notes Substantive Review Notes Substantive Review Notes Substantive Review Problem Ques... Substantive Review Revision Notes The Giving Of Reasons Reading Notes Theory Notes Theory Of Administrative Law Notes Validity And Collateral Challeng...