xs
This website uses cookies to ensure you get the best experience on our website. Learn more

#15034 - Penal Theory - Criminology

Notice: PDF Preview
The following is a more accessible plain text extract of the PDF sample above, taken from our Criminology Notes. Due to the challenges of extracting text from PDFs, it will have odd formatting.
See Original

Ashworth: The State needs a primary rationale/purpose of sentencing

  • Shouldn’t have a single rationale, but giving absolute discretion to sentencers is also inappropriate and inconsistent

  • In Sweden, Desert (Proportionality) is the primary rationale except in identified cases

CJA 2003 s142: Court must have regard to the purposes of sentencing

  • Punishment

  • Reduction of crime (including deterrence)

  • Reform and rehabilitation

  • Public protection

  • Reparation

Hart: Mixed theory

  • Utilitarian aim of crime reduction is the General Justifying Aim of punishment, while justice determines who to punish and to what extent

  • Criticised by Bageric and Braithwaite: unclear when the GJA can be ignored in favour of other considerations

  • VIEW: Neither pure utilitarianism nor pure retributivism can act both as a justification for punishment and for determining the detailed sentence required

  • Punishment is the right of a ruler

  • Punishment must be based on the principle of equality

    • Sentences should be based on the law of retribution (ius talionis)

    • Anything less would be collaborating in the public violation of justice

  • No autonomous creature can be treated as a means for the happiness of others

  • Offenders are rational individuals who choose to commit crimes

  • “by being punished he is honoured as a rational being”

    • Offenders cannot be treated as animals who must be rendered harmless or deterred and reformed by the system

  • No need to have literal equality of punishment, but rather corresponding deserts

    • Deterrence and rehabilitation can be results of retributive punishment, but not the prime purposes of it

  • Tonry (1993): This conflicts with parsimony and the reduction of suffering

    • Wouldn’t impose the most economical or least severe punishment available

  • Feinberg (1994): Punishment doesn’t only affect the offender

    • Not only is the effect hard to measure, but it also has effects on the innocent family

  • Walker (1991): Exact commensurability is unattainable, proportionality is a “ladder with rungs that are both sliding and elastic” in order to consider culpability

Von Hirsch: Doing Justice (1976)

  • Sentencing should be primarily concerned with seriousness

  • REJECTS the talionic view of desert theory

Von Hirsch: Past or Future Crimes (1986)

  • 2 grounds for punishment (bifurcated rationale)

    • Crime prevention

      • This avoids the absolutist view that punishment is required for censure even if it served no preventive purpose (as pointed about by Kant)

      • The hard treatment “registers disapprobation”

    • Censure

      • Normative censure is an appeal to moral reasoning

Von Hirsch: Censure and Sanctions (1993)

  • Further developed the bifurcated view

    • Moral (normative) censure was now seen as the primary purpose of punishment

      • Victim: Acknowledges that the perpetrator caused harm to the victim

      • Perpetrator: Conveys “disapprobation of the person punished”

      • 3rd parties: Gives them a reason to avoid such conduct because it is presented as being morally wrong

    • Hard treatment provides a “prudential reason that is tied to, and supplements, the normative reason conveyed by penal censure”

      • Ashworth and Von Hirsch (2005): Punishment has a secondary preventive role via hard treatment, but is justified by normative retributivism

    • People are neither angels (normative censure would suffice) nor beasts (only hard treatment would be effective), so both are needed

  • Censure is part of recognizing the offender’s moral autonomy

    • Rejects the theory that punishment rectifies the “unfair advantage” gained by the offender through offending

  • Why proportionality?

    • It is part of “everyday notions of justice” that “penalties should fairly reflect the degree of blame-worthiness of the conduct involved”

    • Provides some degree of guidance: “penalties should be graded in severity to reflect the gravity of the offences involved”

  • Desert must be applied parsimoniously

    • Proportionality can be used to scale penalties down

  • Ashworth and Von Hirsch (2005): Allow for “limited deviations” to achieve other pressing objectives of punishment

  • Success of desert theory depends on whether the punishment is accurately scaled to the crime, not by the amount of crime reduction

  • Bottoms: This is a type of “forward-looking communicative theory of punishment”

CJA 1991: placed an emphasis on proportionality in sentencing

  • Dingwall (2008): Although the focus has been modified, there is still a need for proportionate or “commensurate” punishments (CJA 2003 s153)

  • Ordinal proportionality

    • Ranking offences in relative seriousness to each other

      • Wolfgang’s studies suggest that people have largely similar intuitive ranking of offence seriousness, with some contentious issues

    • Ranking punishments in relative severity

  • Cardinal proportionality

    • Relating the ranked offences with the scale of punishment

    • Von Hirsch: Excessively harsh punishments can be avoided by choosing the right anchoring point

      • Limited by basic human rights

      • Should use the lowest sentence which satisfies desert (but not just in order to save costs, which is the utilitarian view)

  • Jareborg and Von Hirsch: Seriousness and severity can be determined according to the “living standard” framework in terms of the impact on important interests

    • Severity is not a matter of “subjective unpleasantness”

    • ISSUE (Walker): Sentencing SHOULD take into account individual sensitivity

  • Von Hirsch (1993): A desert model “permits reliance on other factors (including those of crime prevention) for some purposes—e.g. for deciding among sanctions of comparable onerousness”

Ashworth: Even opponents to this theory agree that wholly disproportionate sentences are unacceptable, so this is relevant at least in determining broad ranges

  • Proportionality sets the outer boundaries by determining what is disproportionate

    • So that even if they would otherwise be justified by rehabilitation or deterrence, disproportionate sentences cannot be used

    • Within the range, the exact sentence is determined based on other principles while ensuring parsimony (increase severity to meet other purposes but no more than necessary)

  • Von Hirsch: Conduct of similar seriousness should get approximately the same sentences

    • Parity cannot be disregarded for other purposes (e.g. deterrence)

  • Penalties are scaled according to proportionality but upward deviations are permitted in exceptional circumstances to prevent an “intolerable level of crime”

    • Although gross deviations wouldn’t be allowed

  • Scaling should be determined by empirical data about public views, not theory

    • Public has consistent views on general severity

    • Would improve compliance if the public sees the CJS as being fair and consistent with their own moral values

  • Allows for deviations

    • Inconspicuous deviations via policy and judges on grounds of societal interests

    • Larger deviations if necessary to obtain crime-control benefits which outweigh the costs, which can also be used to vary the form of sentences

  • ISSUE (Kolber): Difficult to quantitatively compare the benefit of crime control and lost compliance due to the violation of desert principles

  • ISSUE (Frase): Not possible to reach a consensus on “precise exchange rates” for sentencing and offence severity

  • Von Hirsch: It would be difficult to maintain a narrow margin and identify cases which warrant deviation

    • ISSUE: This would be similar to the special provisions for dangerous offenders

  • Walker: Punishment, Danger and Stigma (1980)

    • Pure retributivism wouldn’t take into account mitigating or aggravating factors

    • There is a need to incapacitate dangerous offenders from repeating their offences for the sake of public protection

    • It is simplistic to apply but doesn’t pursue a practical aim (unlike other theories which aim at reducing crime)

    • BUT desert theory does help to ensure consistency

  • Walker (1992)

    • Unclear if the offender would understand the moral disapproval being conveyed

      • Even if he does, why is there a duty to convey it?

    • Problem of “sensibility” (identified by Bentham)

    • Spacing problem:

Government’s sentencing aims are generally outcome-focused

  • E.g. Youth Justice: aimed at reducing offending

  • Focus on public protection, rehabilitation, not just deterrence

  • PBR and privatization are concerned with costs (and maybe rehabilitation), which is a utilitarian approach

Bentham (1789)

  • Utilitarianism is minimizing pain/suffering and maximizing pleasure

    • Majoritarian approach, consequentialist

  • Punishment should only be inflicted if it can prevent greater evil

  • Proportionality is determined by the need to deter, rather than being based on desert

Bagaric (2001)

  • There is room within utilitarian theory for proportionality since that promotes consistency and fairness whereas disproportionality would undermine the system

    • However, proportionality is not absolute (unlike in retributivism) and can be retreated from if necessary to pursue a more pressing utilitarian objective of punishment

  • Utilitarianism can recognise rights as promoting utility, although they would not be given special weight or seen as inviolable

  • Easton: might result in disproportionate punishment to achieve a positive outcome (e.g. public protection), or recommend punishment where it wouldn’t be appropriate

    • Could technically allow for punishment of the innocent if it would contribute to the public good

  • Dworkin:...

Unlock the full document,
purchase it now!
Criminology